Fallacies of definition
Fallacies of definition are the various ways in which definitions can fail to explain terms. The phrase is used to suggest an analogy with an informal fallacy.<ref>Kale, Rekhaa (2015-10-25). "BLS LOGIC 1: CHAPTER 8. DEFINITION". BLS LOGIC 1. Retrieved 2020-07-21.</ref> Definitions may fail to have merit, because they: are overly broad, use obscure or ambiguous language, or contain circular reasoning; those are called fallacies of definition.<ref>Gibbon, Guy (2013). Critically Reading the Theory and Methods of Archaeology: An Introductory Guide. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 9780759123427.</ref> Three major fallacies are: overly broad, overly narrow, and mutually exclusive definitions,<ref name="Potter">Potter, Karl H. (1991). Presuppositions of India's Philosophies, p.87. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 9788120807792. "Under-extension", "over-extension", and "mutual exclusion".</ref> a fourth is: incomprehensible definitions,<ref>Chakraborti, Chhanda (2007). Logic: Informal, Symbolic and Inductive, p.54-5. PHI Learning. ISBN 9788120332485. "Too wide", "too narrow", "incomprehensible", and "conflicting".</ref> and one of the most common<ref name="H&D"/> is circular definitions.<ref>Schipper, Edith Watson and Schuh, Edward (1960). A First Course in Modern Logic, p.24. Routledge. "Incongruous", "circular", "negative", and "obscure or figurative".</ref>
Circularity
If one concept is defined by another, and the other is defined by the first, this is known as a circular definition, akin to circular reasoning: neither offers enlightenment about what one wanted to know.<ref name="the-logical-fallacies">"Circular Definition". Stephen's Guide to the Logical Fallacies. Accessed September 2, 2014.</ref> "It is a fallacy because by using a synonym in the definiens the reader is told nothing significantly new."<ref name="H&D"/>
A straightforward example would be to define Jew as "a person believing in Judaism", and Judaism as "the religion of the Jewish people", which would make Judaism "the religion of the people believing in Judaism".
Incongruity: overly broad or narrow
A definition intended to describe a given set of individuals fails if its description of matching individuals is incongruous: too broad (excessively loose with parameters) or too narrow (excessively strict with parameters). For example, "a shape with four sides of equal length" is not a sufficient definition for square, because squares are not the only shapes that can have four sides of equal length; rhombi do as well. Likewise, defining rectangle as "a shape with four perpendicular sides of equal length" is inappropriate because it is too narrow, as it describes only squares while excluding all other kinds of rectangles, thus being a plainly incorrect definition.
If a cow were defined as an animal with horns, this would be overly broad (including goats, for example), while if a cow were defined as a black-and-white quadruped, this would be both overly narrow (excluding: all-black, all-white, all-brown and white-brown cows, for example)<ref name="Potter"/> and overly broad (including Dalmatians, for example).
Obscurity
Definitions can go wrong by using ambiguous, obscure, or figurative language. This can lead to circular definitions. Definitions should be defined in the most prosaic form of language to be understood, as failure to elucidate provides fallacious definitions.<ref name="the-logical-fallacies"/> Figurative language can also be misinterpreted. For example, golden eyes in a biography may lead the reader to think that the person was fictional.
An example of obscurity is Samuel Johnson's definition for oats: "A grain, which in England is generally given to horses, but in Scotland supports the people."<ref name=oats>Johnson, Samuel (1755), "Oats", A Dictionary of the English Language</ref> The thing defined (oats) should be pointed out rather than remain obscure.
Mutual exclusivity
The definition completely excludes what is being defined. For example, a cow might be defined as a flying animal with no legs.<ref name="Potter"/> In reality a cow has legs and cannot fly, but this example claims to define a cow using a definition that is opposite to what a cow actually is. "Cow" and "flying animal with no legs" are mutually exclusive to each other: they cannot refer to the same thing.
Self-contradictory requirements
This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (August 2014) |
Definitions may fail by imposing conflicting requirements, making it impossible for them to apply to anything at all. For example, a cow being defined as a legless quadruped, or the term dynamic equilibrium – equilibrium state cannot be dynamic. These requirements may also be mutually exclusive.[citation needed]
Definist fallacy
The definist fallacy is a logical fallacy, coined by William Frankena in 1939, that involves the definition of one property in terms of another.<ref name="BunninYu2008">Bunnin, Nicholas; Yu, Jiyuan (2008), The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy, John Wiley & Sons, p. 165, ISBN 978-0-470-99721-5</ref>[clarification needed]
See also
Lua error in mw.title.lua at line 318: bad argument #2 to 'title.new' (unrecognized namespace name 'Portal').
- Equivocation
- Fallacy – Argument that uses faulty reasoning
- Fallacy of division
- Fallacy of equivocation
- Fallacies of inference
- Formal fallacy
- Inscrutability of reference
- Persuasive definition